Can a proof be just words?












1












$begingroup$


I suppose this is a question about mathematical convention. In a problem in Introduction to Probability by Bertsekas and Tsitsiklis, they ask the reader to prove an identity. But then their proof is just using words:



enter image description here



In mathematics, why is this allowed? Can you say that this is more correct a proof that is, "Oh, it's obvious!" or "Just keep distributing $A$ over and over ad nauseum and you get the term on the right"?



I'm not trolling. I'm genuinely curious as to how thorough one must be when using words as proof.










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$








  • 2




    $begingroup$
    I think it's great. It's airtight, erudite, and to the point. You want to keep notation under control in mathematical exposition.
    $endgroup$
    – ncmathsadist
    50 mins ago






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    There are a few formulæ to denote the objects. I'll add that you can you've really understood a problem if you can solve it in words.
    $endgroup$
    – Bernard
    46 mins ago
















1












$begingroup$


I suppose this is a question about mathematical convention. In a problem in Introduction to Probability by Bertsekas and Tsitsiklis, they ask the reader to prove an identity. But then their proof is just using words:



enter image description here



In mathematics, why is this allowed? Can you say that this is more correct a proof that is, "Oh, it's obvious!" or "Just keep distributing $A$ over and over ad nauseum and you get the term on the right"?



I'm not trolling. I'm genuinely curious as to how thorough one must be when using words as proof.










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$








  • 2




    $begingroup$
    I think it's great. It's airtight, erudite, and to the point. You want to keep notation under control in mathematical exposition.
    $endgroup$
    – ncmathsadist
    50 mins ago






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    There are a few formulæ to denote the objects. I'll add that you can you've really understood a problem if you can solve it in words.
    $endgroup$
    – Bernard
    46 mins ago














1












1








1





$begingroup$


I suppose this is a question about mathematical convention. In a problem in Introduction to Probability by Bertsekas and Tsitsiklis, they ask the reader to prove an identity. But then their proof is just using words:



enter image description here



In mathematics, why is this allowed? Can you say that this is more correct a proof that is, "Oh, it's obvious!" or "Just keep distributing $A$ over and over ad nauseum and you get the term on the right"?



I'm not trolling. I'm genuinely curious as to how thorough one must be when using words as proof.










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$




I suppose this is a question about mathematical convention. In a problem in Introduction to Probability by Bertsekas and Tsitsiklis, they ask the reader to prove an identity. But then their proof is just using words:



enter image description here



In mathematics, why is this allowed? Can you say that this is more correct a proof that is, "Oh, it's obvious!" or "Just keep distributing $A$ over and over ad nauseum and you get the term on the right"?



I'm not trolling. I'm genuinely curious as to how thorough one must be when using words as proof.







formal-proofs






share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question











share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question










asked 59 mins ago









gwggwg

9301921




9301921








  • 2




    $begingroup$
    I think it's great. It's airtight, erudite, and to the point. You want to keep notation under control in mathematical exposition.
    $endgroup$
    – ncmathsadist
    50 mins ago






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    There are a few formulæ to denote the objects. I'll add that you can you've really understood a problem if you can solve it in words.
    $endgroup$
    – Bernard
    46 mins ago














  • 2




    $begingroup$
    I think it's great. It's airtight, erudite, and to the point. You want to keep notation under control in mathematical exposition.
    $endgroup$
    – ncmathsadist
    50 mins ago






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    There are a few formulæ to denote the objects. I'll add that you can you've really understood a problem if you can solve it in words.
    $endgroup$
    – Bernard
    46 mins ago








2




2




$begingroup$
I think it's great. It's airtight, erudite, and to the point. You want to keep notation under control in mathematical exposition.
$endgroup$
– ncmathsadist
50 mins ago




$begingroup$
I think it's great. It's airtight, erudite, and to the point. You want to keep notation under control in mathematical exposition.
$endgroup$
– ncmathsadist
50 mins ago




1




1




$begingroup$
There are a few formulæ to denote the objects. I'll add that you can you've really understood a problem if you can solve it in words.
$endgroup$
– Bernard
46 mins ago




$begingroup$
There are a few formulæ to denote the objects. I'll add that you can you've really understood a problem if you can solve it in words.
$endgroup$
– Bernard
46 mins ago










4 Answers
4






active

oldest

votes


















5












$begingroup$

Exactly as thorough as you would have to be using any other kinds of symbols. It's just that vast messes of symbols are hellish for humans to read, but sentences aren't. Adding symbols to something doesn't make it more rigorous, less likely to be wrong, or really anything else. Symbols are useful for abbreviating in situations where this adds clarity, and making complex arguments easier to follow, but shouldn't be used where they do not help in this regard.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$





















    2












    $begingroup$

    Yes they can and I'm of the opinion that symbolism and notation should be avoided unless it serves to simply the presentation of the material or to perform calculations. For example you want to cut a cube so that each face has a three by three grid of smaller cubes similar to the Rubix cube and with a little thought and experimentation once might conjecture that six is the minimal number of cuts. The best proof of this that I know of is simply "Consider the faces of the center cube." They require six cuts because there are six faces and it follows immediately. No symbols or calculation but still logical and mathematically sound.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$













    • $begingroup$
      I think your example proof only shows that 6 is a lower bound, not that it is a minimum.
      $endgroup$
      – Paŭlo Ebermann
      3 mins ago



















    1












    $begingroup$

    Natural language for expressing mathematical statements can be indeed vague and ambigous. However, when you study mathematics, one thing you will usually learn at the beginning is how to use mathematical terminology in a rigid, unambigous way (at least for communication with other people trained in mathematical terminology). This process takes usually some time if you are not a genius (I guess it took me about two years at the university until I became reasonable fluent), so unfortunately I fear I cannot tell you a small set of rules which kind of language is "right" for mathematical proofs, and which is "wrong".



    So IMHO the answer is clearly "yes, words are fine, when used correctly by a trained expert". Amazingly, one could say the same about proofs using formal symbols.



    Note that historically, before the 18th century, proofs using natural language was the de facto standard in mathematics. The symbolics we often use today was developed in the 18th and 19th century.






    share|cite|improve this answer








    New contributor




    Doc Brown is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
    Check out our Code of Conduct.






    $endgroup$





















      0












      $begingroup$

      Two points:



      (i) Historically, all proofs were done in words—the use of standardised symbols is a surprisingly recent development. This is obscured a bit because a modern edition of, say, Euclid's Elements is likely to have had the words translated into modern notation.



      (ii) Before symbols can be used they have to be defined, and ultimately that definition will be in words. It's easy to forget this, especially with ones that we use all the time and learnt in childhood. But, for example, we once had to learn that $2+3=5$ was short for "Two things together with three things is the same as five things".



      Though a lot of us learnt instead that $2+3=5$ meant "Three things added to two things makes five things".



      Now, these two definitions are different. One makes $2+3$ into an operation done to $2$, and treats $=$ as an instruction to carry it out; the other says that the number on the right has the same value as the expression on the left. The notation, though, doesn't make this distinction, and it's possible to spend years using the $=$ sign as though it meant "put the result of the operation on the left on the right".



      So in this case we've got one string of symbols, $2+3=5$, a correct definition and a misleading definition. And how do we clarify which is the correct definition of the symbols? By choosing which verbal definition we mean.



      Of course, more advanced symbols will most likely have some mathematical symbols in their definitions—but ultimately, we'll get back to words.






      share|cite









      $endgroup$













        Your Answer





        StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
        return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
        StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
        StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
        });
        });
        }, "mathjax-editing");

        StackExchange.ready(function() {
        var channelOptions = {
        tags: "".split(" "),
        id: "69"
        };
        initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

        StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
        // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
        if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
        StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
        createEditor();
        });
        }
        else {
        createEditor();
        }
        });

        function createEditor() {
        StackExchange.prepareEditor({
        heartbeatType: 'answer',
        autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
        convertImagesToLinks: true,
        noModals: true,
        showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
        reputationToPostImages: 10,
        bindNavPrevention: true,
        postfix: "",
        imageUploader: {
        brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
        contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
        allowUrls: true
        },
        noCode: true, onDemand: true,
        discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
        ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
        });


        }
        });














        draft saved

        draft discarded


















        StackExchange.ready(
        function () {
        StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3079966%2fcan-a-proof-be-just-words%23new-answer', 'question_page');
        }
        );

        Post as a guest















        Required, but never shown

























        4 Answers
        4






        active

        oldest

        votes








        4 Answers
        4






        active

        oldest

        votes









        active

        oldest

        votes






        active

        oldest

        votes









        5












        $begingroup$

        Exactly as thorough as you would have to be using any other kinds of symbols. It's just that vast messes of symbols are hellish for humans to read, but sentences aren't. Adding symbols to something doesn't make it more rigorous, less likely to be wrong, or really anything else. Symbols are useful for abbreviating in situations where this adds clarity, and making complex arguments easier to follow, but shouldn't be used where they do not help in this regard.






        share|cite|improve this answer









        $endgroup$


















          5












          $begingroup$

          Exactly as thorough as you would have to be using any other kinds of symbols. It's just that vast messes of symbols are hellish for humans to read, but sentences aren't. Adding symbols to something doesn't make it more rigorous, less likely to be wrong, or really anything else. Symbols are useful for abbreviating in situations where this adds clarity, and making complex arguments easier to follow, but shouldn't be used where they do not help in this regard.






          share|cite|improve this answer









          $endgroup$
















            5












            5








            5





            $begingroup$

            Exactly as thorough as you would have to be using any other kinds of symbols. It's just that vast messes of symbols are hellish for humans to read, but sentences aren't. Adding symbols to something doesn't make it more rigorous, less likely to be wrong, or really anything else. Symbols are useful for abbreviating in situations where this adds clarity, and making complex arguments easier to follow, but shouldn't be used where they do not help in this regard.






            share|cite|improve this answer









            $endgroup$



            Exactly as thorough as you would have to be using any other kinds of symbols. It's just that vast messes of symbols are hellish for humans to read, but sentences aren't. Adding symbols to something doesn't make it more rigorous, less likely to be wrong, or really anything else. Symbols are useful for abbreviating in situations where this adds clarity, and making complex arguments easier to follow, but shouldn't be used where they do not help in this regard.







            share|cite|improve this answer












            share|cite|improve this answer



            share|cite|improve this answer










            answered 54 mins ago









            user3482749user3482749

            3,822417




            3,822417























                2












                $begingroup$

                Yes they can and I'm of the opinion that symbolism and notation should be avoided unless it serves to simply the presentation of the material or to perform calculations. For example you want to cut a cube so that each face has a three by three grid of smaller cubes similar to the Rubix cube and with a little thought and experimentation once might conjecture that six is the minimal number of cuts. The best proof of this that I know of is simply "Consider the faces of the center cube." They require six cuts because there are six faces and it follows immediately. No symbols or calculation but still logical and mathematically sound.






                share|cite|improve this answer









                $endgroup$













                • $begingroup$
                  I think your example proof only shows that 6 is a lower bound, not that it is a minimum.
                  $endgroup$
                  – Paŭlo Ebermann
                  3 mins ago
















                2












                $begingroup$

                Yes they can and I'm of the opinion that symbolism and notation should be avoided unless it serves to simply the presentation of the material or to perform calculations. For example you want to cut a cube so that each face has a three by three grid of smaller cubes similar to the Rubix cube and with a little thought and experimentation once might conjecture that six is the minimal number of cuts. The best proof of this that I know of is simply "Consider the faces of the center cube." They require six cuts because there are six faces and it follows immediately. No symbols or calculation but still logical and mathematically sound.






                share|cite|improve this answer









                $endgroup$













                • $begingroup$
                  I think your example proof only shows that 6 is a lower bound, not that it is a minimum.
                  $endgroup$
                  – Paŭlo Ebermann
                  3 mins ago














                2












                2








                2





                $begingroup$

                Yes they can and I'm of the opinion that symbolism and notation should be avoided unless it serves to simply the presentation of the material or to perform calculations. For example you want to cut a cube so that each face has a three by three grid of smaller cubes similar to the Rubix cube and with a little thought and experimentation once might conjecture that six is the minimal number of cuts. The best proof of this that I know of is simply "Consider the faces of the center cube." They require six cuts because there are six faces and it follows immediately. No symbols or calculation but still logical and mathematically sound.






                share|cite|improve this answer









                $endgroup$



                Yes they can and I'm of the opinion that symbolism and notation should be avoided unless it serves to simply the presentation of the material or to perform calculations. For example you want to cut a cube so that each face has a three by three grid of smaller cubes similar to the Rubix cube and with a little thought and experimentation once might conjecture that six is the minimal number of cuts. The best proof of this that I know of is simply "Consider the faces of the center cube." They require six cuts because there are six faces and it follows immediately. No symbols or calculation but still logical and mathematically sound.







                share|cite|improve this answer












                share|cite|improve this answer



                share|cite|improve this answer










                answered 37 mins ago









                CyclotomicFieldCyclotomicField

                2,2181313




                2,2181313












                • $begingroup$
                  I think your example proof only shows that 6 is a lower bound, not that it is a minimum.
                  $endgroup$
                  – Paŭlo Ebermann
                  3 mins ago


















                • $begingroup$
                  I think your example proof only shows that 6 is a lower bound, not that it is a minimum.
                  $endgroup$
                  – Paŭlo Ebermann
                  3 mins ago
















                $begingroup$
                I think your example proof only shows that 6 is a lower bound, not that it is a minimum.
                $endgroup$
                – Paŭlo Ebermann
                3 mins ago




                $begingroup$
                I think your example proof only shows that 6 is a lower bound, not that it is a minimum.
                $endgroup$
                – Paŭlo Ebermann
                3 mins ago











                1












                $begingroup$

                Natural language for expressing mathematical statements can be indeed vague and ambigous. However, when you study mathematics, one thing you will usually learn at the beginning is how to use mathematical terminology in a rigid, unambigous way (at least for communication with other people trained in mathematical terminology). This process takes usually some time if you are not a genius (I guess it took me about two years at the university until I became reasonable fluent), so unfortunately I fear I cannot tell you a small set of rules which kind of language is "right" for mathematical proofs, and which is "wrong".



                So IMHO the answer is clearly "yes, words are fine, when used correctly by a trained expert". Amazingly, one could say the same about proofs using formal symbols.



                Note that historically, before the 18th century, proofs using natural language was the de facto standard in mathematics. The symbolics we often use today was developed in the 18th and 19th century.






                share|cite|improve this answer








                New contributor




                Doc Brown is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                Check out our Code of Conduct.






                $endgroup$


















                  1












                  $begingroup$

                  Natural language for expressing mathematical statements can be indeed vague and ambigous. However, when you study mathematics, one thing you will usually learn at the beginning is how to use mathematical terminology in a rigid, unambigous way (at least for communication with other people trained in mathematical terminology). This process takes usually some time if you are not a genius (I guess it took me about two years at the university until I became reasonable fluent), so unfortunately I fear I cannot tell you a small set of rules which kind of language is "right" for mathematical proofs, and which is "wrong".



                  So IMHO the answer is clearly "yes, words are fine, when used correctly by a trained expert". Amazingly, one could say the same about proofs using formal symbols.



                  Note that historically, before the 18th century, proofs using natural language was the de facto standard in mathematics. The symbolics we often use today was developed in the 18th and 19th century.






                  share|cite|improve this answer








                  New contributor




                  Doc Brown is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                  Check out our Code of Conduct.






                  $endgroup$
















                    1












                    1








                    1





                    $begingroup$

                    Natural language for expressing mathematical statements can be indeed vague and ambigous. However, when you study mathematics, one thing you will usually learn at the beginning is how to use mathematical terminology in a rigid, unambigous way (at least for communication with other people trained in mathematical terminology). This process takes usually some time if you are not a genius (I guess it took me about two years at the university until I became reasonable fluent), so unfortunately I fear I cannot tell you a small set of rules which kind of language is "right" for mathematical proofs, and which is "wrong".



                    So IMHO the answer is clearly "yes, words are fine, when used correctly by a trained expert". Amazingly, one could say the same about proofs using formal symbols.



                    Note that historically, before the 18th century, proofs using natural language was the de facto standard in mathematics. The symbolics we often use today was developed in the 18th and 19th century.






                    share|cite|improve this answer








                    New contributor




                    Doc Brown is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                    Check out our Code of Conduct.






                    $endgroup$



                    Natural language for expressing mathematical statements can be indeed vague and ambigous. However, when you study mathematics, one thing you will usually learn at the beginning is how to use mathematical terminology in a rigid, unambigous way (at least for communication with other people trained in mathematical terminology). This process takes usually some time if you are not a genius (I guess it took me about two years at the university until I became reasonable fluent), so unfortunately I fear I cannot tell you a small set of rules which kind of language is "right" for mathematical proofs, and which is "wrong".



                    So IMHO the answer is clearly "yes, words are fine, when used correctly by a trained expert". Amazingly, one could say the same about proofs using formal symbols.



                    Note that historically, before the 18th century, proofs using natural language was the de facto standard in mathematics. The symbolics we often use today was developed in the 18th and 19th century.







                    share|cite|improve this answer








                    New contributor




                    Doc Brown is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                    Check out our Code of Conduct.









                    share|cite|improve this answer



                    share|cite|improve this answer






                    New contributor




                    Doc Brown is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                    Check out our Code of Conduct.









                    answered 15 mins ago









                    Doc BrownDoc Brown

                    1115




                    1115




                    New contributor




                    Doc Brown is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                    Check out our Code of Conduct.





                    New contributor





                    Doc Brown is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                    Check out our Code of Conduct.






                    Doc Brown is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                    Check out our Code of Conduct.























                        0












                        $begingroup$

                        Two points:



                        (i) Historically, all proofs were done in words—the use of standardised symbols is a surprisingly recent development. This is obscured a bit because a modern edition of, say, Euclid's Elements is likely to have had the words translated into modern notation.



                        (ii) Before symbols can be used they have to be defined, and ultimately that definition will be in words. It's easy to forget this, especially with ones that we use all the time and learnt in childhood. But, for example, we once had to learn that $2+3=5$ was short for "Two things together with three things is the same as five things".



                        Though a lot of us learnt instead that $2+3=5$ meant "Three things added to two things makes five things".



                        Now, these two definitions are different. One makes $2+3$ into an operation done to $2$, and treats $=$ as an instruction to carry it out; the other says that the number on the right has the same value as the expression on the left. The notation, though, doesn't make this distinction, and it's possible to spend years using the $=$ sign as though it meant "put the result of the operation on the left on the right".



                        So in this case we've got one string of symbols, $2+3=5$, a correct definition and a misleading definition. And how do we clarify which is the correct definition of the symbols? By choosing which verbal definition we mean.



                        Of course, more advanced symbols will most likely have some mathematical symbols in their definitions—but ultimately, we'll get back to words.






                        share|cite









                        $endgroup$


















                          0












                          $begingroup$

                          Two points:



                          (i) Historically, all proofs were done in words—the use of standardised symbols is a surprisingly recent development. This is obscured a bit because a modern edition of, say, Euclid's Elements is likely to have had the words translated into modern notation.



                          (ii) Before symbols can be used they have to be defined, and ultimately that definition will be in words. It's easy to forget this, especially with ones that we use all the time and learnt in childhood. But, for example, we once had to learn that $2+3=5$ was short for "Two things together with three things is the same as five things".



                          Though a lot of us learnt instead that $2+3=5$ meant "Three things added to two things makes five things".



                          Now, these two definitions are different. One makes $2+3$ into an operation done to $2$, and treats $=$ as an instruction to carry it out; the other says that the number on the right has the same value as the expression on the left. The notation, though, doesn't make this distinction, and it's possible to spend years using the $=$ sign as though it meant "put the result of the operation on the left on the right".



                          So in this case we've got one string of symbols, $2+3=5$, a correct definition and a misleading definition. And how do we clarify which is the correct definition of the symbols? By choosing which verbal definition we mean.



                          Of course, more advanced symbols will most likely have some mathematical symbols in their definitions—but ultimately, we'll get back to words.






                          share|cite









                          $endgroup$
















                            0












                            0








                            0





                            $begingroup$

                            Two points:



                            (i) Historically, all proofs were done in words—the use of standardised symbols is a surprisingly recent development. This is obscured a bit because a modern edition of, say, Euclid's Elements is likely to have had the words translated into modern notation.



                            (ii) Before symbols can be used they have to be defined, and ultimately that definition will be in words. It's easy to forget this, especially with ones that we use all the time and learnt in childhood. But, for example, we once had to learn that $2+3=5$ was short for "Two things together with three things is the same as five things".



                            Though a lot of us learnt instead that $2+3=5$ meant "Three things added to two things makes five things".



                            Now, these two definitions are different. One makes $2+3$ into an operation done to $2$, and treats $=$ as an instruction to carry it out; the other says that the number on the right has the same value as the expression on the left. The notation, though, doesn't make this distinction, and it's possible to spend years using the $=$ sign as though it meant "put the result of the operation on the left on the right".



                            So in this case we've got one string of symbols, $2+3=5$, a correct definition and a misleading definition. And how do we clarify which is the correct definition of the symbols? By choosing which verbal definition we mean.



                            Of course, more advanced symbols will most likely have some mathematical symbols in their definitions—but ultimately, we'll get back to words.






                            share|cite









                            $endgroup$



                            Two points:



                            (i) Historically, all proofs were done in words—the use of standardised symbols is a surprisingly recent development. This is obscured a bit because a modern edition of, say, Euclid's Elements is likely to have had the words translated into modern notation.



                            (ii) Before symbols can be used they have to be defined, and ultimately that definition will be in words. It's easy to forget this, especially with ones that we use all the time and learnt in childhood. But, for example, we once had to learn that $2+3=5$ was short for "Two things together with three things is the same as five things".



                            Though a lot of us learnt instead that $2+3=5$ meant "Three things added to two things makes five things".



                            Now, these two definitions are different. One makes $2+3$ into an operation done to $2$, and treats $=$ as an instruction to carry it out; the other says that the number on the right has the same value as the expression on the left. The notation, though, doesn't make this distinction, and it's possible to spend years using the $=$ sign as though it meant "put the result of the operation on the left on the right".



                            So in this case we've got one string of symbols, $2+3=5$, a correct definition and a misleading definition. And how do we clarify which is the correct definition of the symbols? By choosing which verbal definition we mean.



                            Of course, more advanced symbols will most likely have some mathematical symbols in their definitions—but ultimately, we'll get back to words.







                            share|cite












                            share|cite



                            share|cite










                            answered 7 mins ago









                            timtfjtimtfj

                            1,333318




                            1,333318






























                                draft saved

                                draft discarded




















































                                Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


                                • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

                                But avoid



                                • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

                                • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


                                Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


                                To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




                                draft saved


                                draft discarded














                                StackExchange.ready(
                                function () {
                                StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3079966%2fcan-a-proof-be-just-words%23new-answer', 'question_page');
                                }
                                );

                                Post as a guest















                                Required, but never shown





















































                                Required, but never shown














                                Required, but never shown












                                Required, but never shown







                                Required, but never shown

































                                Required, but never shown














                                Required, but never shown












                                Required, but never shown







                                Required, but never shown







                                Popular posts from this blog

                                How to label and detect the document text images

                                Vallis Paradisi

                                Tabula Rosettana